At Dorf on law, Eric Segall: Of Judge Jackson, Originalism, and a Tale of Three Scholars. From the introduction:
During her confirmation hearing, Judge Kentaji Brown Jackson seemed to self-identify as an originalist. She said the following: “The adherence to text is a constraint on my authority. I’m trying to figure out what those words mean, as they were intended by the people who wrote them.”
These comments, of course, were met with delight across the vast Federalist Society landscape and with despair among non-originalists of all stripes. The two best examples are a pair of essays by, on one hand, Professor John McGinnis, and on the other, Conor Casey and Adrian Vermule. Make no mistake, Casey and Vermule have the better of the argument by far.
Let's start with McGinnis. He delighted in Jackson's words, arguing that her testimony further entrenched originalism in our legal and political culture. ...
...
McGinnis observed that Democratic senators did not push back strongly on Judge Jackson's statements (mostly for political reasons) and concluded that "beneath the din of partisanship, the Jackson confirmation hearings show that originalism is becoming our law, even if its contours remain up for debate."
Casey and Vermeule had almost the opposite different reaction to the hearing. ...
Casey and Vermeule began by noting "if this is a victory for originalism, it is a Pyrrhic victory of epic proportions." They then summarized the problem as follows:
If and when most judicial nominees, liberal and conservative, Democratic and Republican, assent to some form of originalism, it will come at a steep price for originalists: Their method will be shown to do nothing at all, save, perhaps, providing a jargon in which to rationalize decisions reached on other grounds. It will become clear — even as the justices resolutely deny it — that all the real work, in hard cases of constitutional interpretation, is done by implicit or explicit commitments of political morality. Moreover, the Pyrrhic victory for originalism will be a defeat for the nation at large, diminishing transparency about the real grounds of judicial decisions and exacerbating cynicism about constitutional law.
Casey and Vermule are exactly right on all points. First, originalism, like all or almost all theoretical pre-commitments by the Justices, does almost no work in most constitutional law cases that get to the Court. Second, the "real work" of the Justices in cases involving "constitutional interpretation" involves applying their values, politics, and life experiences to the hard issues the Court has to resolve, not historical or textual analysis. Third, because the Justices talk the talk of text and history, however, instead of being open about what really drives their decisions, Casey and Vermule are spot on that as greater numbers of judges and academics pay lip service to originalism, we lose more and more transparency about the "real grounds of judicial decisions."
UPDATE: In The Hill, a related essay from Andrew Koppelman (Northwestern): Ketanji Brown Jackson’s originalism. From the introduction:
Constitutional originalists have been doing a victory lap after Ketanji Brown Jackson declared, in her confirmation hearing, “I believe that the Constitution is fixed in its meaning. I believe that it’s appropriate to look at the original intent, original public meaning, of the words when one is trying to assess because, again, that’s a limitation on my authority to import my own policy.” This, Georgetown Prof. Randy Barnett declared, “legitimates originalism. . . . she has affirmed that it is the norm.”
Other commentators more soberly noted that originalism now takes so many different forms that it no longer means much. It certainly does not entail the conservative political implications that the early proponents of originalism, such as Edwin Meese and Robert Bork, hoped for. Jackson was signaling to her new colleagues that she speaks the same language as they, but that doesn’t limit what she will say. You can say almost anything in original-speak.
Originalism has three central problems. It doesn’t really constrain judges. Even if it did, it would do so randomly and chaotically. But in fact, as it has been deployed in the Supreme Court, it is a fraud: The self-styled originalists don’t really care about historical evidence. They manipulate it to reach the results they find politically congenial, and then parade their virtue by saying they are merely following the law.
This essay, like others in a similar vein, seems to suffer from inconsistent claims: either (a) original meaning is indeterminate and so isn't useful as a way of constraining judges, or (b) purportedly originalist judges are frauds in that they ignore the best historical evidence to follow their political preferences. These are both potentially powerful critiques but they're inconsistent so the critic needs to pick one or the other. (Lawyers can argue in the alternative but scholars shouldn't.)
As to (a), I think it may be true as to some clauses and some applications, but it's not generally true; there are many constitutional points on which the original meaning is reasonably clear, especially once one recognizes that originalism doesn't require that there be no possible contrary argument, but only that one should pick the most plausible original meaning. As to (b), I think this point is basically irrelevant to the question of whether originalism is the right approach. If judges aren't doing originalism right, the response should be to criticize them on that ground. Also, (b) seems a very strong claim ("fraud"!) that should have very substantial evidence to back it up, but the essay's only evidence is that Justice Alito has a different view of the original meaning of the free exercise clause from the author. (Apparently the original meaning of the free exercise clause is, in Professor Koppelman's view, so clear that disagreement with him amounts to "fraud," notwithstanding his earlier claim that original meaning is indeterminate.)
FURTHER UPDATE: Eric Segall has an additional related post: Recency Bias and the Supreme Court as a Broken Institution. From the introduction:
The reality is that the times we live in are not unusual when it comes to controversies surrounding the Court. Recency bias has played a large role in the thinking of Court watchers that we are in more difficult times than ever when it comes to the Justices' decisions. But the truth is that the Court has been broken for well over 150 years. The Court needs to be fixed not because it is too conservative or at times too liberal but because we should not allow unelected, life-tenured judges to play such a large role in our country's politics. And that problem is anything but new both in terms of degree and kind.
Unlike his prior post, I mostly agree with this one. The Court has often, wrongly, acted as a political institution. But unlike Professor Segall, I see originalism as part of the solution. If the Court would apply the Constitution's text, and refrain from decisions based on policy preferences, that would be be a substantial step in the right direction.