Prof. Eric Segall has written a post, “The Boys are Back: Section 3, Trump's Failed Disqualification, and the Irrelevancy of Originalism,” criticizing a new article by Profs. William Baude and Michael Stokes Paulsen in which they vehemently reject the Supreme Court’s unanimous decision—Trump v. Andersen (2024)—which itself rejected their now-famous contention that Section 3 of the 14th Amendment bars Donald Trump from the presidency.
At the outset, I would agree with Prof. Segall that Trump v. Andersen was correctly decided, although my reasons (here) are entirely different from his. And, like him, I do not accept original-public-meaning-originalism as a valid theory of constitutional interpretation (see, here). Rather, I consider myself to be a constitutional textualist. In my mind, both originalism and textualism require courts, with certain very narrow exceptions, to interpret the Constitution in accordance with the plain meaning of its terms. (Originalism entertains a rebuttable presumption that constitutional texts have time-dated meanings different from current meanings, while textualism, in my understanding, entertains a rebuttable presumption that those texts have meanings identical to current meanings.)
Baude and Paulsen argue that, unlike the Court’s opinions in other “great” cases they cite, the opinions in Trump v. Andersen ignored the plain original meaning of Section 3. In contrast, Segall asserts: “The ‘great’ cases cited with approval by [Baude and Paulsen] were demonstrably much more concerned with consequences than the words on the page or ancient historical events.” The contention that originalism is irrelevant because it relies on text and history would apply equally well (or ill) to textualism. Therefore, I want to demonstrate the weakness of that contention.
Segall seeks confirmation in one of those “great” decisions: Justice Robert Jackson’s concurring opinion in Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, which dealt with President Truman’s seizure of privately-owned steel mills to provide war materiel for the Korean conflict. Segall notes that Justice Jackson wrote:
Just what our forefathers did envision, or would have envisioned had they foreseen modern conditions, must be divined from materials almost as enigmatic as the dreams Joseph was called upon to interpret for Pharaoh. A century and a half of partisan debate and scholarly speculation yields no net result, but only supplies more or less apt quotations from respected sources on each side of any question. They largely cancel each other. (343 US at 634-635, footnote omitted.)
Segall asserts: “A more direct and complete condemnation of originalism is hard to imagine.” But it is a truism to observe, as Jackson did, that we can never know with any certainty how people who are now dead would have decided an issue that they never thought about when they were alive. That truism is not in any way a condemnation of originalism or textualism.
Immediately after the passage Segall quotes, Jackson’s concurrence examines the structure of “a workable government” (343 US at 635) created by the text of the Constitution. Jackson sets forth his famous three-part analysis of lawful presidential authority: it is maximal when the president’s own authority is added to congressional authorization of presidential action; in a middling state when the president acts on his or her own authority without the approval or disapproval of Congress; at its lowest ebb when the president’s actions are incompatible with the express or implied will of Congress.
Having set forth this three-part analytical framework, which follows logically from the text of Articles I and II, Jackson turns to the seizure of the steel mills. He decides that the seizure falls within the third classification, because, although Congress enacted three statutes authorizing presidential seizure of private property, Pres. Truman had concededly not complied with any of those three statutes. Therefore, the seizure was incompatible with the will of Congress.
Having made that determination, Jackson considers whether the seizure can nevertheless be sustained because it “is within [the president’s] domain and beyond control by Congress.” (343 US at 640.) To begin, Jackson rejects the argument that the first sentence of Article II grants to the president “all the executive powers of which this Government is capable.” (Id.) One reason for that rejection is that, if that argument is correct, there would have been no reason to delegate explicitly certain powers to the president: “[I]t is difficult to see why the forefathers bothered to add several specific items, including some trifling ones.” (343 US at 640-641.) Jackson’s position, contrary to Segall, is here explicitly based on constitutional text, i.e., on Sections 2 and 3 of Article II.
Moreover, regarding the unlimited executive power claimed by Truman, Jackson says that “[t]he example of such unlimited executive power that must have most impressed the forefathers was the prerogative exercised by George III, and the description of its evils in the Declaration of Independence leads me to doubt that they were creating their new Executive in his image.” (343 US at 641.) Thus, Jackson explicitly relies on “ancient historical events” that Segall denigrates as irrelevant to important, historic Court opinions.
In rejecting the argument that the president’s power as commander in chief of the armed forces authorized the seizure, Jackson states:
There are indications that the Constitution did not contemplate that the title Commander in Chief of the Army and Navy will constitute him also Commander in Chief of the country, its industries and its inhabitants. He has no monopoly of "war powers," whatever they are. While Congress cannot deprive the President of the command of the army and navy, only Congress can provide him an army or navy to command. It is also empowered to make rules for the "Government and Regulation of land and naval Forces," by which it may, to some unknown extent, impinge upon even command functions. (343 US at 643-644, emphasis in original.)
Again, Jackson relies on explicit constitutional text in dismissing Truman’s contention.
Pres. Truman also invoked the presidential oath, which requires the president to “take Care that the Laws be faithfully executed[.]” But Jackson contrasts this language with that of the Fifth Amendment, which prohibits the deprivation of property “without due process of law[.]” (343 US at 646.) Relying explicitly on the Amendment’s text, Jackson rejected Truman’s position.
Finally, Truman argued that the president must have inherent powers “to deal with a crisis or an emergency according to the necessities of the case, the unarticulated assumption being that necessity knows no law.” (Id.) Justice Jackson rejected that argument as well:
The appeal, however, that we declare the existence of inherent powers ex necessitate to meet an emergency asks us to do what many think would be wise, although it is something the forefathers omitted. They knew what emergencies were, knew the pressures they engender for authoritative action, knew, too, how they afford a ready pretext for usurpation.… Aside from suspension of the privilege of the writ of habeas corpus in time of rebellion or invasion … , they made no express provision for exercise of extraordinary authority because of a crisis. I do not think we rightfully may so amend their work, and, if we could, I am not convinced it would be wise to do so[.] (343 US at 649-650, footnotes omitted.)
This is, again, an instance where Jackson relies explicitly on constitutional text—or, more precisely, the absence of constitutional text—to dispose of the president’s contention.
One final, and perhaps most important, point. The very first paragraph of Jackson’s concurrence states:
The opinions of judges, no less than executives and publicists, often suffer the infirmity of confusing the issue of a power's validity with the cause it is invoked to promote, of confounding the permanent executive office with its temporary occupant. The tendency is strong to emphasize transient results upon policies -- such as wages or stabilization -- and lose sight of enduring consequences upon the balanced power structure of our Republic. (343 US at 634.)
The warning against confusing “a power’s validity” with “the cause it is invoked to promote” strikes me as the precise opposite of Segall’s notion that Jackson’s concurrence minimizes the importance of text and history, while maximizing the importance of the consequences of a particular decision. Prof. Segall is all about cause, while Justice Jackson focuses on validity grounded in text and history.